Open Access
How to translate text using browser tools
24 April 2020 Philosophy of Ethnobiology: Understanding Knowledge Integration and Its Limitations
David Ludwig, Charbel N. El-Hani
Author Affiliations +
Abstract

Ethnobiology has become increasingly concerned with applied and normative issues, such as climate change adaptation, forest management, and sustainable agriculture. Applied ethnobiology emphasizes the practical importance of local and traditional knowledge in tackling these issues but thereby also raises complex theoretical questions about the integration of heterogeneous knowledge systems. The aim of this article is to develop a framework for addressing questions of integration through four core domains of philosophy—epistemology, ontology, value theory, and political theory. In each of these dimensions, we argue for a model of “partial overlaps” that acknowledges both substantial similarities and differences between knowledge systems. While overlaps can ground successful collaboration, their partiality requires reflectivity about the limitations of collaboration and co-creation. By outlining such a general and programmatic framework, the article aims to contribute to developing “philosophy of ethnobiology” as a field of interdisciplinary exchange that provides new resources for addressing foundational issues in ethnobiology and also expands the agenda of philosophy of biology.

Introduction

Ethnobiology has become widely concerned with questions of knowledge integration in complex multi-stakeholder settings. While ethnobiologists document biological knowledge of local communities, they also increasingly emphasize the practical relevance of this knowledge for addressing socio-ecological challenges from health and food security to labor conditions and the preservation of biocultural heritage (Cuerrier et al. 2015; Wolverton 2013; Wyndham et al. 2011). This emphasis on the local expertise of non-academic actors has put ethnobiologists at the center of wider collaborative developments in the life sciences that aim for “co-creation,” “co-leadership,” “co-management,” “multi-stakeholder approaches,” “participatory action research,” “participatory design,” “upstream engagement,” “transdisciplinarity,” and so on (Davidson-Hunt et al. 2012; Gavin et al. 2015; Saslis -Lagoudakis and Clarke 2013; Wolverton et al. 2014a).

While ethnobiological contributions to such multi-stakeholder interactions have been reflected in a turn towards “applied ethnobiology” (Armstrong and Veteto 2015; Sillitoe 2006; Whyte 2018; Wolverton 2013), it would be a mistake to assume that they reduce the need for careful theoretical reflection. On the contrary, applied and especially collaborative perspectives in ethnobiology raise complex philosophical questions about the prospects and limitations of integrating knowledge systems of heterogeneous stakeholders. First, there is the epistemological challenge (Marlor 2010; Wilson 2008) that traditional communities and academically trained scientists often rely on very different methods for producing and validating knowledge, from spiritual norms of ecological engagement to computational modeling of ecological dynamics. Second, there is the ontological challenge (Ellen 2016; Ludwig 2018a) of collaborating in the light of very different assumptions about reality as reflected in anthropological accounts of issues, such as the mental life of plants and forests (Kohn 2013) or the status of rivers as persons (Hutchison 2014). Third, there is the ethical challenge (Anderson 1996; Whyte 2015; Wolverton et al. 2016) that epistemic and ontological assumptions are intertwined with different value systems, such as contrasting ways of thinking about moral responsibilities between human and non-human agents. Finally, there is the political challenge (Ludwig 2016a; Nadasdy 2003) that stakeholders often hold very different positions of power to enforce their epistemological, ontological, and ethical perspectives in collaborative practice.

Despite the interdisciplinary orientation of ethnobiological research, none of these epistemological, ontological, and normative challenges have led to a sustained interaction between ethnobiology and academic philosophy. The aim of this article is to outline a framework for bringing ethnobiology together with philosophical research to address fundamental challenges of multi-stakeholder processes. The next section introduces a general framework of “partial overlaps” that contrasts with overly optimistic accounts of philosophical universalism and pessimistic perspectives on cross-cultural incommensurability. The following sections develop this framework in four philosophical core domains of ontology, epistemology, value theory, and political theory. The final section provides a synthesizing discussion about the role of philosophical reflectivity for ethnobiological research.

A Methodology of Partial Overlaps

Global challenges, such as climate change (Wolverton et al. 2014b), deforestation (Alves and Albuquerque 2012), and food security (Nolan and Pieroni 2014), have to be addressed through the inclusion of heterogeneous stakeholders. A crucial element in the development of multi-stakeholder processes is the recognition of local expertise about environments and sustainable practices (Byskov 2017; Whyte and Crease 2010). For example, Indigenous hunters will often be able to monitor endangered species, traditional farmers have rich expertise about sustainable agroforestry, and local fishers tend to be the first to notice changes in marine, estuarine, and riverine ecosystems.

Ethnobiology can play an important role in spelling out this idea of local expertise by documenting the complexity of traditional knowledge beyond academic research. For example, Berlin and Berlin's (1996:3) classical account, Medical Ethnobiology of the Highland Maya of Chiapas, not only provides detailed documentation of a specialized body of local knowledge but also explicitly argues “that the ethnobiological knowledge of traditional peoples conforms in many respects to basic scientific principles.” Emphasizing both the complexity of traditional knowledge and its compatibility with modern science, ethnobiology appears to be an ideal resource for transdisciplinary knowledge integration that synthesizes the expertise of very different stakeholders in developing better responses to socio-ecological challenges (Albuquerque et al. 2017; Nabhan 2009, 2016).

While ethnobiology provides resources for knowledge integration, there has also been increased concern about the limitations and adverse effects of integration projects. For example, Nadasdy's (2003) influential critique of traditional ecological knowledge (TEK) has emphasized that optimistic visions of knowledge integration often obscure differences between stakeholders and thereby reproduce hierarchies between scientists and local communities in the negotiation of practice and policy (Lertzman 2009). Often, holders of TEK need to prove the value of their knowledge by showing that it holds up to the methodological and epistemological criteria of academic researchers. As a consequence, TEK is required to be validated through academic criteria, but academic research is not regarded in need of validation through compliance with TEK. This imbalance can create what philosophers have called “testimonial injustice” (Anderson 2012; Fricker 2007; Wanderer 2011) and contribute to practices that treat TEK as a resource for novel data while ignoring aspects of TEK that challenge the assumptions of academically trained scientists.

As Ludwig and Poliseli (2018) have argued, this situation can be described as a dilemma between assimilation and division. On the one hand, critics of overly optimistic integration ideals like Nadasdy are correct to point out the danger of downplaying differences between knowledge systems and therefore obscuring unique features of ethnobiological knowledge (see also El-Hani and de Ferreira Bandeira 2008). On the other hand, overly pessimistic accounts of incommensurable knowledge systems are equally problematic from both theoretical and political perspectives. First, philosophers have questioned whether the idea of entirely incommensurable knowledge systems is coherent in the first place (Davidson 1984; Putnam 1981). While anthropological discussions of the ontological turn (Holbraad and Pedersen 2017) often postulate a “radical alterity” of “different worlds” (Alberti et al. 2011; Henare et al. 2007; cf. Graeber 2015), this literature does little in addressing theoretical worries about the coherence of incommensurability and radical metaphysical claims about different worlds often remain philosophically obscure. Furthermore, claims about incommensurable worlds also come with political risks as they seem to undermine the very possibility of productive interaction between heterogeneous stakeholders. As a result, an exclusive focus on difference returns to what Agrawal (1995) has famously criticized as the “divide between Indigenous and scientific knowledge” that creates not only artificial boundaries but can also contribute to marginalizing traditional knowledge in policy and practice through the assumption of insurmountable differences (Hunn 2014).

The aim of this article is to develop a nuanced framework for analyzing the relations between knowledge systems that avoids a biased focus on either differences or similarities through a framework of “partial overlaps.” On the one hand, we propose to develop an analysis of overlaps that provide common ground for collaboration and mutual understanding. The following sections argue that such overlaps can be identified across core philosophical domains, including ontological assumptions about the biological world, epistemological strategies for achieving knowledge about biota and environments, and normative reasoning about moral relations between human and non-human agents.

While an analysis of overlaps clarifies shared resources for collaboration, we propose a complementary analysis of the partiality of such overlaps. Although there may be substantial overlaps in fundamental assumptions of traditional and academic knowledge systems, there will often also remain substantial differences along ontological, epistemological, and value dimensions. For each of these dimensions, the relations between two knowledge systems (K1 and K2) can be visualized through intersecting sets in which the intersection (K1 ∩ K2) represents shared assumptions, while the relative complements (K1 \ K2 ^ K2 \ K1) represent (ontological, epistemological, and value) assumptions that are unique to knowledge systems (Figure 1).

We argue that such an idea of partial overlaps can provide methodological tools for addressing relations between foundational assumptions between (ethno) biological knowledge systems. The following sections develop this idea of partial overlaps as a methodological tool through four philosophical core domains of ontology, epistemology, value theory, and political theory. In each of these cases, we argue that a framework of partial overlaps allows more nuanced analyses of foundational issues in ethnobiology that avoid shortcomings of universalism and relativism.

Figure 1.

Simple representation of partially overlapping knowledge systems through intersecting sets that include shared ontological, epistemological, value resources (intersection), as well as unique elements (relative complements).

img-z4-1_03.jpg

While this article develops a theoretical and philosophical perspective, it also aims to provide an applicable framework for addressing foundational issues in ethnobiological practice. Each of the following sections is supplemented by a short example of application from our own fieldwork in two fishing villages on the north shore of the state of Bahia, Brazil, situated in the estuary of a large river (Itapicuru): Siribinha (ca. 500 inhabitants) and Poças (ca. 700 inhabitants) (El-Hani and Almeida, In press). While fishing communities in the region are gradually disappearing due to the growth of the tourism industry and declining catches resulting from overfishing, pollution, and other environmental threats, in these villages, we still find a living fishing culture (Brazilian artisanal fishing culture is an emergent cultural product from native Tupinamba and Portuguese influences, with some African contributions [Ott 1944]). Young people are still learning the traditional fishing practices but are also increasingly relying on work in touristic activities to supplement their income. Knowledge is flowing across generations and these communities use at least a dozen different fishing techniques and show a wealth of ethnobiological knowledge, not only about the animals they capture (fishes, crustaceans, mollusks), but also about medicinal plants and the local environments. Understandably, it has previously attracted the attention of ethnobiologists (e.g., Costa-Neto 2000; Costa-Neto and Marques 2000).

Partial Overlaps in Ontologies

Ontology is one of the core domains of philosophy and is concerned with the question of what exists (Chalmers 2011; Quine 1948; Sider 2011). As debates about the “ontological turn” have moved to the center of anthropological theory (Holbraad and Pedersen 2017), ethnobiologists have also become increasingly concerned with cross-cultural relations among ontological assumptions (Daly et al. 2016). In current anthropological theory, emphasis on difference tends to dominate recognition of similarity and many influential anthropologists focus on cases of radical alterity, such as ontological commitments to shamanic transformations (Viveiros de Castro 2014) or thinking forests (Kohn 2013).

Ludwig (2016a) has suggested that ethnotaxonomic research provides a different but complementary angle for investigating cross-cultural relations among ontologies. Ethnotaxonomy provides a “bottom-up” strategy that starts with small-scale ontological differences—for instance, concerning categories of animals and plants—rather than the more common anthropological “top-down” strategy that proceeds from the most salient cases of deep ontological difference (Ellen 2006; Hunn 2014). By putting ontological relations under the “microscope of ethnotaxonomy,” the methodology of partial overlaps can be articulated more clearly. There are many salient cases of ontological convergence, as illustrated by cross-cultural agreement on the boundaries of many biological species. These cases of ontological convergence play an important role in ethnotaxonomy and are especially prominent in Berlin's (1992) universalist program. Furthermore, Berlin also provides a metaphysical justification of these convergences by appealing to “discrete, discontinuous chunks of biological reality” (Berlin 1992:81) that can be further specified through philosophical accounts of natural kinds and their grounding in causal networks and property clusters (Khalidi 2013; Slater 2015; see Ludwig 2018a, 2018b for application to ethnobiology).

While there is need for substantial philosophical discussion of cross-cultural similarities between categories, ethnobiologists have increasingly qualified claims of cross-cultural convergence. Nabhan (2016:27) clearly expresses wider developments of the field when arguing for a focus on “the anomalies, the unique cultural expressions, and the collisions of dissonant taxonomic structures.” Looking at such dissonant taxonomic structures provides a microcosmos of ontological difference, as culturally unique concerns and local environmental factors influence what distinctions between animals and plants are being drawn. At the same time, the very fact that dissonant taxonomic structures can often be qualified as “anomalies” illustrates that widespread convergence is also found among ethnotaxonomies.

Addressing both cross-cultural similarities and differences in the categorization of animals and plants provides an important application of the wider idea of partial overlaps. Indeed, there are cross-cultural ontological similarities that provide the basis for collaborative ethnobiological practices which would often not be possible without joint recognition of the same biological species. However, there are also ontological differences that matter because they often reflect different priorities and concerns about biological and ecological properties (Ludwig 2018a). Rather than pushing for a universalist emphasis on cross-cultural similarities or a relativist emphasis on differences, a model of partial overlaps suggests a more nuanced picture of the relations among ontologies.

Can this picture of partial overlaps be extended from categories of animals and plants to wider ontological issues as commonly debated by anthropologists in the context of the “ontological turn”? It can indeed be fruitful to explore the framework of partial ontological overlaps in the context of these wider issues. Much of the anthropological literature has focused on salient cases of ontological difference but it would be a mistake to assume that there are no substantial overlaps. For example, consider Kohn's (2013) influential discussion in How Forests Think. In part, fascination with Kohn's discussion comes from the ontological difference between the Runa of Ecuador's upper Amazon, who take forests to be thinking agents, and Western scholars who often reserve “thinking” for a much narrower set of organisms, such as humans and some other mammals. In part, however, fascination with Kohn's account also comes from sufficient ontological overlap. The idea of thinking forests is not so alien that Kohn's descriptions become unintelligible to non-Runa readers. On the contrary, part of the fascination with thinking forests is that they do appear as a genuine ontological option to which many readers can at least partly relate. Indeed, radical expansions of the realm of cognition are very much part of the Western intellectual heritage and are also reflected in current controversies about plant cognition (Adams 2018; Segundo-Ortin and Calvo 2018).

Of course, this does not mean that ontological assumptions can always be integrated, as shown by deep cross-cultural differences that are often emphasized by proponents of the “ontological turn” in anthropology. For example, Viveiros de Castro's (2014) discussion of shamanic transformation aims at fundamentally different metaphysical perspectives on the relation between human and non-human that challenge optimistic accounts of ontological integration. Again, accounts of ontological overlaps need to be complemented with analyses of their partiality that leave room for deep cross-cultural disagreement about ontological matters.

To sum up, the idea of partial overlaps provides a useful guide for thinking about ontological relationships from fine-grained questions about the boundaries of plants and animals to general ontological issues, such as animism and the boundaries of “cognition.” It, therefore, constitutes an alternative to the one-sided focus on ontological similarity that has dominated large parts of the Berlinian tradition of ethnotaxonomy and the focus on ontological difference that dominates large parts of current anthropological theory. As such, it provides ethnobiologists with a sharper and more nuanced framework for addressing ontological relationships in multi-stakeholder processes.

Application

Partially overlapping ontologies can be found in our field study in traditional fishing villages in Brazil. Consider, for instance, the ethnobiology of Buteogallus aequinoctialis (Rufous Crab-hawk, locally known as gacici, a near-threatened species [see BirdLife International 2018]). Cross-cultural taxonomic convergence is clear: fishing communities and academic zoologists uncontroversially refer to the same species, despite having different knowledge about it. Ethnobiological research leads to new insights about gacici, as there is almost nothing published on the biology of the species. It is from traditional knowledge that we learn, for example, that this hawk calls when the tide turns: their calls are used by the fishermen as indication that the tide will be low for some time and they need to retrieve the captured fish. This is a clear inference from traditional knowledge, even expressed in a local saying, “Gacici cantou, a maré vazou [Gacici sang, the tide turned].” Other insights derive from academic research rather than traditional knowledge. For example, the presence of the species in the mangroves, as a specialist top predator, is a bioindicator of how well-conserved the mangroves are, despite use by the villagers, which may be sustainable, at least to some extent. Epistemic productivity of knowledge integration can also be shown, due both to the sum of unique inferences from each knowledge system and to novel inferences using insights from both systems. For instance, one may conjecture that gacici calls when the tide turns to signal for a conspecific, with which it hunts together, the availability of crabs for foraging. The calls may also be used as signals shared by a couple, as some raptors are known to form lasting couples and hunt together. This is, at least, a hypothesis worth testing. Our field studies also show the partiality of overlaps in taxonomy. If we consider, for instance, the two local species of sandpipers (small and large sandpipers—maçaricos pequeno and grande), we will be able to see a correspondence between two ethnospecies and at least 11 scientific species. Small sandpipers include Actitis macularis, Arenaria interpres, Calidris alba, Calidris pusilla, Charadrius collaris, and Charadrius semipalmatus, while large sandpipers include Numenius hudsonicus, Tringa melanoleuca, Tringa semipalmata, Pluvialis squatarola, and Limnodromus griseus.

Partial Overlaps in Epistemology

It has become widely argued in contemporary philosophy of science that “the scientific method” in singular does not exist (Andersen and Hepburn 2016; Laudan 1983). Of course, there are common characteristics of scientific practices, such as experimentation, modeling, and mathematization, but none of them provide necessary and sufficient conditions of science that are applicable from cultural anthropology to quantum physics. While the lack of a simple demarcation criterion for science is hardly a new philosophical insight, it has important implications for thinking about epistemic relations between traditional and academic knowledge in ethnobiology.

Under the assumption of a general demarcation criterion, one could aim to investigate whether local ethnobiological knowledge systems meet the essential criterion for science. Without a clear demarcation criterion, comparisons of knowledge systems lead to more ambiguous diagnoses, as traditional knowledge shares some but not all epistemic features with academic biological knowledge. Given an expansion of the idea of “partial overlaps” from ontology to epistemology, this is not a surprising outcome. On the one hand, ethnobiological research often presupposes a substantial overlap in epistemic resources. For example, consider an ethnobiologist going into the field with a traditional expert to learn about local plants and their cultural significance. Such practices would simply not be possible without substantial overlap in epistemic resources, such as joint reliance on observation or similar ways of reasoning about ecological relations. As classics in epistemology from Wittgenstein (1953) to Davidson (1984) have stressed, disagreement can only be intelligible on the basis of substantial agreement. Collaborative practices in ethnobiology provide vivid illustrations of this point, as joint engagement with biocultural diversity would simply not be possible without substantial agreement in observing and reasoning about biota and environments.

Even if collaborative approaches in ethnobiology presuppose shared epistemic resources, they are also often confronted with deep and unexpected differences. For example, consider Marlor's (2010) study of tensions between Canadian biologists from the Department of Fisheries and Oceans (DFO) and commercial clam diggers of the Kwakwaka'wakw First Nation. As Marlor describes in detail, tensions were at least in part grounded in different methodological standards. DFO biologists assessed clam abundance through randomly selected sample areas of the beach that were standardized through straight perimeters and assessed through an equally standardized procedure of digging clams. In contrast, Kwakwaka'wakw assessed clam abundance through harvest outcomes that were not standardized but affected by different individual styles and contexts of clam digging. Marlor is careful in providing a nuanced picture of the epistemic virtues and vices (Ludwig 2017) of both strategies. The standardized DFO method had drawbacks, such as being inapplicable to certain areas (e.g., high clam abundance near rock walls that did not allow the required straight perimeters) and excluding individual expertise of experienced clam diggers, but also had epistemic virtues that were important for DFO researchers, such as transparency and replicability of methods.

An adequate account of epistemic relations among heterogeneous stakeholders requires acknowledgment of similarities in epistemic resources, as well as differences, that limit collaboration and co-creation. A starting point for such an account of partially overlapping epistemologies has been recently developed in philosophy of ecology by Poliseli (2018). Poliseli's account of explanation and understanding in ecology avoids the specification of one general methodology of ecological research but instead develops the idea of toolboxes of context-sensitive heuristics that allow researchers to grasp complex ecological dynamics. As Ludwig and Poliseli (2018) have argued, this metaphor of toolboxes of heuristics can be used to develop a more nuanced account of the epistemic relations between traditional and academic ecological knowledge: it would be a mistake to think that stakeholders always operate with identical or entirely distinct epistemic tools. Instead, some tools will be largely identical. Some will be related but noticeably different. And some tools will only be found in one of the toolboxes.

In spelling out this metaphor of toolboxes, it is helpful to start with salient cases of similarity and difference. When looking for similarities between epistemic tools, the most obvious examples come from general cognitive abilities, such as visual perception and inductive reasoning. Consider a local hunter and an academically trained ornithologist trying to assess the status of a local bird population. Both of them will rely on observations of birds and inductive generalizations from these observations. Indeed, these very general cognitive abilities are universally shared among human agents and it is hard to even imagine any biological knowledge that is not grounded in some of these shared basic epistemic tools.

When looking for differences, it is helpful to start with more high-level epistemic traditions that have been shaped by epistemic communities over the course of several generations. In the context of European science, for example, one of the most important epistemic traditions is mathematization (Dijksterhuis 1961) with a long history from the mathematical roots of the scientific revolution to current methods of computational modeling. Considering the highly specialized character of mathematical methods in current scientific practices and their increased reliance on digital technologies, it is indeed not difficult to identify salient contrasts with knowledge production in Indigenous and other local communities. Furthermore, differences can also be approached from another direction by looking for epistemic traditions of local communities that are often the result of hundreds of years of adaptation and co-evolution with local environments (Albuquerque et al. 2015; Berkes 2017).

To sum up, the metaphor of toolboxes avoids a simple dichotomy between universally shared epistemic resources and incommensurable epistemologies by treating them as endpoints on a gradual spectrum. In fact, these endpoints are usually no more than idealizations, as it is typically not difficult to locate some similarities and some differences between the epistemic tools of stakeholders. For example, general cognitive capacities like visual perception and inductive reasoning may be the best candidates for universally shared epistemic resources but also interact with their local socio-ecological embedding (Atran and Medin 2008). Indeed, the “theory-ladenness of observation” (Bogen 2009; Brewer and Lambert 2001) has been widely discussed in philosophy of science, as observing certain phenomena through scientific instruments, such as microscopes or telescopes, often requires careful theoretical training. Similar experiences are familiar in ethnobiological research, as ethnobiologists often have to acquire intimate familiarity with local knowledge systems in order to understand what a local farmer is seeing in the field or to understand what an Indigenous hunter is hearing in the forest.

Just as cross-culturally shared epistemic resources, such as visual perception, involve some differences in practice, highly specialized epistemic tools will usually still involve some cross-cultural similarities. For example, it is true that current scientific methods of mathematical modeling in ecology are the product of an epistemic tradition that contrasts with the ecological reasoning of many Indigenous communities. However, numerical cognition does not only play a role in Western science but is also a part of Indigenous accounts of environments, as one can see in estimates of population sizes or population trends (Gordon 2004). The idea of overlapping epistemologies should not be misunderstood, as suggesting a neat division between tools that are essentially the same and tools that are essentially incommensurable. On the contrary, relations between epistemic tools tend to be more complex and involve both opportunities and limitations that need to be carefully addressed in ethnobiological practice.

Application

Partial overlaps in epistemology can be found in our studies of epistemological practices in the traditional fishing village of Siribinha. The villagers use epistemic tools, such as causal explanations, just as do academic researchers. They explain the regular disappearance of a bivalve (Anomalocardia brasiliana, locally called massunim) due to the causal effect of freshwater that periodically enters the estuary due to heavy rains upstream and kills it. They also explain that the massunim reappears because it remains buried until freshwater is “washed away” by the highest sea tides. The villagers also identify mechanisms to explain phenomena. They explain the high availability of snooks (Centropomus sp., one of the most common fish in the area, locally named robalo) in some periods due to a number of factors, such as: (i) freshwater coming down the river and displacing the juveniles growing in the mangroves; (ii) the muddy waters that make it difficult for the fish to see the nets used to capture them; despite (iii) the flickering lights in the net caused by the bioluminescence from what they call “água-viva,” which can be either jellyfish or some metaphor stemming from the fact that, as they say, the water “burns” through sparks (from an academic scientific perspective, this bioluminescence probably originates from Noctiluca sp.). They mention several components causally interacting with one another, organized in space and time, as in a scientific mechanistic model. But there are also divergences between traditional and scientific epistemic tools showing the partiality of epistemological overlaps. For instance, our fieldwork data illustrate how general cognitive abilities, such as inductive reasoning from observation, are sensitive to socio-ecological and cultural circumstances. While academic researchers strive for multiple, replicable tests that allow them to weigh evidence for and against a claim, a fisher may need one single, crucial test to be convinced to accept a new fishing artifact or technique. As a local fisherman (called Zé) told us, if he tests a net and successfully captures fish, he will not doubt the net when it seems to fail, because this simply means that there are no fish, not that the net is faulty. This difference may be grounded in the distinct outcomes sought by a fisher and an academic researcher. A fisher may be in the position to accept one crucial test because he or she deals with quite concrete outcomes, say, whether fish are captured or not by a net, while a researcher, worrying about how well his or her methods provide reliable evidence on rather abstract things like an underlying causal structure, is more likely to feel that more tests are generally needed.

Partial Overlaps in Value Systems

Sustainability has become a dominant concept at the intersection of normative and empirical concerns about socio-ecological dynamics. While some sustainability-related ideas can be traced back to early modern (Caradonna 2014) or even ancient philosophy (Gomis et al. 2011), the rise of the term “sustainability” is a product of the late twentieth century and has been most commonly associated with the Brundtland (WCED 1987) report Our Common Future, published by the World Commission on Environment and Development in 1987. For example, Hansson (2010:274) suggests that “it was in the 1987 report Our Common Future…that sustainability became a central concept in environmental policies. The importance of this report in late twentieth century environmental policies cannot be overstated.”

While explicit theorizing on sustainability is a relatively recent phenomenon, it has become common to appeal to Indigenous and traditional practices as inspirations and models for sustainable practices. In fact, the Brundtland report already argued that tribal and Indigenous “lifestyles can offer modern societies many lessons in the management of resources in complex forest, mountain and dryland ecosystems” (WCED 1987:12). Furthermore, it is by no means a coincidence that academic debates about traditional ecological knowledge (TEK) became institutionalized in the same time period (Johannes 1989), providing a bridge between ethnobiological research on local biological knowledge and applied concerns about sustainability in conservation management and wider policy debates.

The co-evolution of discourses about sustainability and TEK can motivate an optimistic vision of co-creation on the basis of converging reasoning about moral responsibilities towards environments. The sustainability concept moves academic research beyond traditional visions of “value-free science” (Douglas 2009; Kincaid et al. 2007; Ludwig 2016b) and fosters transdisciplinary practices in which moral responsibilities and wider value questions are integrated with empirical research. As such, sustainability also promises to move academic research closer to TEK, which never employed a clear dichotomy between “facts” and “values” and always treated knowledge about environments as a fundamentally moral issue. Furthermore, such an account of convergence also seems to support meaningful co-creation that recognizes holders of TEK as experts who can teach scientists how to weave moral responsibility and environmental stewardship into biological and ecological research.

There is certainly some truth to this optimistic vision, which has played an important role in creating awareness for Indigenous and traditional values in conservation practices and environmental policy (Johnson et al. 2016; Kealiikanakaoleohaililani and Giardina 2016). At the same time, stories about complementarity in sustainability can be misleading and outright harmful if they contribute to a neglect of tensions between heterogeneous value systems (Whyte 2015). First, environmental practices of local and traditional communities are highly diverse and blanket characterizations of TEK as sustainable can mislead about this complexity through a simplistic and romanticized picture of sustainable TEK. Second, characterizations of TEK as sustainable also require critical reflectivity about how different value systems can lead to different understandings and operationalizations of “sustainability.”

Consider what Holden et al. (2014) describe as the four primary dimensions of sustainable development in the Brundtland report (WCED 1987): “safeguarding long-term ecological sustainability, satisfying basic human needs, and promoting intragenerational and intergenerational equity.” As much as these dimensions suggest overlaps with value systems of TEK, there are also salient differences. One difference is that TEK often assumes a complex web of mutual responsibilities between human and non-human actors (Lewis-Jones 2016; Rose 2002) that is not adequately reflected in satisfying basic human needs or human-focused equity concerns. If non-human actors are incorporated into the values of TEK, with both responsibilities and rights, normative reasoning about environmental issues will often depart from Western discourses about sustainable development. Second, sustainability discourses tend to be geared to sustainable growth that remains compatible with long-term ecological sustainability and intergenerational equity. While it has become widely reflected that TEK is far from static and adapted to constant change (Fernández-Llamazares and Reyes-García 2016), accounts of change in TEK tend to be very different from sustainability debates that often aim for balancing economic growth with socio-ecological concerns (Elkington 2013).

Expanding the overall methodology of partial overlaps towards value systems in ethnobiology provides a helpful starting point for avoiding both horns of the dilemma of division and assimilation. On the one hand, the assumption of overlaps avoids a simplistic divide between Indigenous and Western values. Postulating an incommensurable divide is often factually incorrect in ethnobiology where local communities and academic researchers share substantive concerns, such as improving of local livelihoods or preservation of biocultural heritage. Furthermore, neglect of overlaps in value systems can also further the marginalization of TEK by rejecting any common ground for meaningful collaboration in the negotiation of practice and policy. On the other hand, the partiality of such overlaps needs to be addressed carefully to avoid illusions of co-creation that are, in fact, an assimilation of TEK into normative agendas of external researchers and conservation managers. Taking transdisciplinary collaboration seriously requires that ethnobiologists navigate this complex web of relations among values that can provide resources for joint action, but also deep normative tensions that need to be taken seriously.

Application

Partial overlaps in value systems can also be found in traditional Brazilian fishing villages, even in cases of radical alterity. Consider the Caipora, an entity from Tupi-Guarani mythology still important in the Brazilian culture, but certainly not a part of academic scientific ontologies. The Caipora is an entity that protects the forest. He will both act against someone who does something bad to the plants and animals, and provide the capture for the hunters and fishers, provided that there is enough forest preserved, which is a requisite for him to offer his animals. This ontological divergence does not seem to matter much, however, when there is a convergence between a conservation scientist's values and the value systems of a traditional fishing community that relies on Caipora and other similar entities to maintain a sustainable extraction model (Almeida 2013). In several fishing villages where we worked over the years, including Siribinha and Poças, we heard the stories that when a fisherman or fisherwoman misbehaves in the mangroves—that is, his or her actions diverge from what are acceptable practices to the community—Caipora may appear and makes him or her lose their way in the mangroves for days or even weeks. In the Boipeba community (also in Bahia, Brazil), where one of the authors worked in the beginning of the 1990s, this was said to happen when a fisherman extracted too much of the red mangrove (Rhizophora mangle; local name mangue-vermelho) bark to dye boat sails, threatening the tree's survival. A conservation scientist may also be content enough with the traditional idea that Caipora needs territories in order to create animals that are offered to hunters or fishers (Almeida 2013). After all, she is likely to notice the overlap with her own ideas on protected areas. In these cases, we can see how local and academic communities share values regarding ecosystem conservation that may make scientists value Caipora as biocultural heritage that sets norms against unsustainable practices, as illustrated by an excessive collection of mangue-vermelho bark. But differences are all too clear, showing both the partiality of value systems overlap and the intertwining of ontologies and values, because the values underlying the norms against unsustainable practice put to use by the traditional community have little to do with Western notions of sustainability and the value of biodiversity. Rather, they concern a different moral order in which there should be a right kind of balance between humans, mangroves, and mythical creatures like Caipora. The conservation scientist would probably not show the same fear or fright in situations that, for local communities, are signs of the presence of Caipora, because, in part, he or she is not committed to that moral order.

Towards a Political Philosophy of Knowledge Integration

The aim of the previous sections has been to spell out the general idea of partial overlaps through three core domains of philosophy: ontology, epistemology, and value theory. This section adds political philosophy as a fourth dimension by showing how an analysis of partial overlaps can lead to better understanding of political dynamics among stakeholders who often hold very different positions of power to enforce their ontological, epistemological, and value perspectives in collaborative practice.

Figure 2.

(a) Marginalization can be the product of ignorance towards local knowledge systems. This scenario is typically the starting point for arguments for co-management and widely reflected in ethnobiology. (b) Marginalization can also occur when local knowledge systems are recognized only where they sufficiently overlap with the (ontological, epistemological, value) assumptions of academically trained scientists. (c) Recognition of both overlap and differences avoids the problems of 2a and 2b but raises new political questions about how differences should be addressed in policy and practice.

img-z12-4_03.jpg

Figure 2 uses the idea of partial (ontological, epistemic, value) overlaps between knowledge systems to distinguish three modes of marginalization of local knowledge. Mode 2a illustrates the case of marginalization through disregard of the very existence of local knowledge systems. This scenario has been widely discussed and criticized in the anthropological literature on failed modernization. For example, Scott's (1998) famous discussion of the Ujamaa villagization campaign in Tanzania that forced local communities to practice “scientific agriculture,” but ended up leading to soil erosion and dysfunctional village structures. Or think of Lansing's (1991) discussion of the negative effects of the “Green Revolution” in Bali that was driven by the goal to increase yields of rice farming through scientifically based practices, but had catastrophic effects on local farmers through water shortages and pest spread. In both cases, the adverse and unintended consequences for local farmers were a product of ignorance towards local knowledge systems. For example, Scott (1998:226) emphasizes, the

…complete faith in what officials took for ‘scientific agriculture’ on one hand and a nearly total skepticism about the actual agricultural practices of Africans on the other. As a provincial agricultural officer in the Shire (Tchiri) Valley put it, ‘The African has neither the training, skill, nor equipment to diagnose his soil erosion troubles nor can he plan the remedial measures, which are based on scientific knowledge, and this is where I think we rightly come in.'

Lansing documented similar attitudes in Bali that led to the suppression of traditional water management through a system of connected water temples. “The answer to pests was pesticide, not the prayers of priests. Or as one frustrated American irrigation engineer said to me, ‘These people don't need a high priest, they need a hydrologist!'” (Lansing 1991:115).

Ignorance towards local knowledge in the sense of 2a has become widely criticized across the biological sciences and is, in many ways, the starting point of the very project of ethnobiology. In contrast, mode 2b illustrates a more elusive danger of partial recognition that acknowledges local knowledge only insofar as it fits with the (ontological, epistemic, value) assumptions of academic researchers. This scenario has been the target of Nadasdy's (2003) influential critique of knowledge integration and is reflected in Kimmerer's (2012) concern about knowledge mining.

Knowledge mining or the extraction of useful facts from the body of knowledge, without exploration of the cultural context in which they belong, can do a disservice to the information as well as to the culture. Just as gold mining degrades a large area of land for the extraction of what is perceived as valuable ‘ore’ and leave a wasteland in its place, extraction of valuable data from traditional knowledge without consideration of its cultural context can also be damaging. (Kimmerer 2012:322)

Both Nadasdy and Kimmerer focus on the risks of an overly optimistic vision of harmonious co-creation in which different stakeholders bring their diverse resources together and jointly solve socio-ecological challenges.Inmanycasesofco-management of local environments, such a picture is indeed tempting, as local communities possess a wealth of expertise about local environments that can complement the knowledge of academically trained ecologists and conservation managers. However, this integration of local knowledge can reproduce and consolidate unequal power relations if academically trained scientists have the power to decide when to incorporate the local knowledge in research and conservation management.

Moving beyond the limitations of 2b requires recognition of local ontologies, epistemologies, and values even when they differ substantially from academic research. Mode 2c represents this situation in which the intersection provides resources for co-creation and collaboration while the partiality of the overlap leaves room for acknowledging various sources of tension that suggest different actions in concrete contexts. While 2c provides a more comprehensive picture that detects both common ground and tensions, it does not, in itself, provide an answer to the question of how tensions should be addressed. On the contrary, the acknowledgment of different resources emphasizes the possibility of different answers to socio-ecological challenges and the political character of choosing between them when negotiating practices and policies.

In this context, one core philosophical task is to move from a merely theoretical discussion of epistemology and ontology towards an explicitly normative discussion of political epistemology and political ontology of ethnobiology. The question is not merely whether local communities have different methods for knowledge creation and validation or different ontological categories, but rather what role these epistemologies and ontologies should have in negotiations of practice and policy. Following Viveiros de Castro (2014), Ludwig (2016b) suggests “ontological self-determination” as a starting point for addressing these questions. The idea of self-determination of local communities provides a helpful contrast to the opportunistic use of local knowledge that is suggested by mode 2b. Rather than integrating local knowledge only where it is relevant for academic researchers, the idea of self-determination inverts this relation by asking when exogenous epistemic and ontological resources become relevant for the concerns of local communities.

While the idea of epistemological and ontological self-determination provides a useful starting point, it clearly requires further specification and qualification. In political philosophy, articulations of self-determination are often tied to the assumption that policies and practices should be determined by the affected stakeholders themselves (Fraser 2007). In many socio-ecological processes, however, it is far from clear how the group of affected stakeholders should be determined. For example, should adequate frameworks for the preservation of a forest be determined exclusively by local communities that directly interact with the forest? Or even more narrowly only those who live in the forest? Or should everyone be considered a relevant stakeholder in forest conservation as it is a crucial requirement for mitigating global climate change? Addressing such questions requires serious engagement with current political philosophy and debates about adequate “scales of justice” (Fraser 2009).

Conclusion

While ethnobiology has grown into a vibrant interdisciplinary field, it also often remains insufficiently connected with wider theoretical debates (Ludwig 2018c). Lepofsky and Wolverton (2018:454) note that “the reach of ethnobiology remains limited in scope” and argue for the need to increase its “visibility in and relevance to global social-ecological discussions.” Although one may be inclined to think of developments towards “applied ethnobiology” as further diminishing the role of wider theoretical reflection, this article has argued that multi-stakeholder processes raise complex questions that require interaction with core areas of philosophy, from ontology and epistemology to value theory and political philosophy. Developing philosophy of ethnobiology as an interdisciplinary field can overcome this lack of institutionalized exchange and contribute to the development of new intellectual tools for addressing these questions.

The point is not simply to add philosophers to the already heterogenous community (Latulippe 2015; Wyndham et al. 2011) of ethnobiologists, which includes scholars from anthropology, archaeology, botany, cognitive science, cultural geography, ecology, Indigenous studies, sociology, and so on. Rather than leading to further fragmentation of the field, philosophy of ethnobiology can play a synthesizing role that connects underlying issues of knowledge diversity that cut across various disciplines of ethnobiological research. For example, a comprehensive account of partial ontological overlaps will require careful attention to relations between taxonomies, as developed in the biological sciences, and relations between more general metaphysical principles, as discussed in the cultural anthropology of the ontological turn. An analysis of overlapping epistemic toolboxes requires attention to experimental evidence from cognitive science, as much as in-depth qualitative narratives from Indigenous studies. Developing philosophy of ethnobiology can, therefore, contribute to building bridges between heterogeneous disciplinary traditions in ethnobiology and to addressing knowledge integration through self-reflective procedures that do not shy away from fundamental questions regarding knowledge diversity in biology.

Acknowledgments

Charbel El-Hani is thankful to CNPq (grant number 465767/2014-1) and CAPES (grant number 23038.000776/2017-54) for their support of INCT IN-TREE, and to CNPq for support in the form of productivity in the research grant (grant number 303011/2017-3). David Ludwig's research has been supported by an ERC Starting Grant (851004 LOCAL KNOWLEDGE) and a NWO Vidi Grant (V1.Vidi.195.026 ETHNOONTOLOGIES).

References Cited

1.

Adams, F. 2018. Cognition Wars. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 68:20–30. Google Scholar

2.

Agrawal, A. 1995. Dismantling the Divide between Indigenous and Scientific Knowledge. Development and Change 26:413–439. Google Scholar

3.

Alberti, B., S. Fowles, M. Holbraad, Y. Marshall, and C. Witmore. 2011. ‘Worlds Otherwise’ Archaeology, Anthropology, and Ontological Difference. Current Anthropology 52:896–912. Google Scholar

4.

Albuquerque, U. P., P. M. de Medeiros, and A. Casas. 2015. Evolutionary Ethnobiology. In Evolutionary Ethnobiology , edited by U. P. Albuquerque, P. M. de Medeiros, and A. Casas, pp. 1–5. Springer, Dordrecht. Google Scholar

5.

Albuquerque, U. P., M. A. Ramos, W. S. F. Júnior, and P. M. de Medeiros. 2017. Ethnobotany, Science and Society. In Ethnobotany for Beginners , edited by U. P. Albuquerque, M. A. Ramos, W. S. F. Júnior, and P. M. de Medeiros, pp. 57–66. Springer, Cham. Google Scholar

6.

Almeida, M. W. B. 2013. Caipora e outros conflitos ontológicos. Revista de Antropologia da UFSCar 5:7–28. Google Scholar

7.

Alves, R. R. N., and U. P. Albuquerque. 2012. Ethnobiology and Conservation: Why Do We Need a New Journal? Ethnobiology and Conservation 1:1. Google Scholar

8.

Andersen, H., and B. Hepburn. 2016. Scientific Method. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy , edited by E. Zalta. Available at:  https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2016/entries/scientific-method/Google Scholar

9.

Anderson, E. 2012. Epistemic Justice as a Virtue of Social Institutions. Social Epistemology 26:163–173. Google Scholar

10.

Anderson, E. N. 1996. Ecologies of the Heart: Emotion, Belief, and the Environment. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Google Scholar

11.

Armstrong, C. G., and J. R. Veteto. 2015. Historical Ecology and Ethnobiology. Ethnobiology Letters 6:5–7. Google Scholar

12.

Atran, S., and D. L. Medin. 2008. The Native Mind and the Cultural Construction of Nature. MIT Press, Cambridge. Google Scholar

13.

Berkes, F. 2017. Sacred Ecology, 4th edition. Routledge, New York. Google Scholar

14.

Berlin, B. 1992. Ethnobiological Classification. Princeton University Press, Princeton. Google Scholar

15.

Berlin, E., and B. Berlin. 1996. Medical Ethnobiology of the Highland Maya of Chiapas, Mexico. Princeton University Press, Princeton. Google Scholar

16.

BirdLifeInternational.2018. Buteogallusaequinoctialis. TheIUCNRedListofThreatenedSpecies 2018: e.T22695808A131937283. Available at:  https://dx.doi.org/10.2305/IUCN.UK.2018-2.RLTS.T22695808A131937283.en. Accessed on March 1, 2020. Google Scholar

17.

Bogen, J. 2009. Theory and Observation in Science. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy , edited by E. Zalta. Available at:  https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/science-theory-observation/Google Scholar

18.

Brewer, W. F., and B. L. Lambert. 2001. The Theory-Ladenness of Observation and the Theory-Ladenness of the Rest of the Scientific Process. Philosophy of Science 68:S176–S186. Google Scholar

19.

Byskov, M. 2017. Third Wave Development Expertise. Oxford Development Studies 45: 352–365. Google Scholar

20.

Caradonna, J. L. 2014. Sustainability: A History. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Google Scholar

21.

Chalmers, D. 2011. Verbal Disputes. Philosophical Review 120:515–566. Google Scholar

22.

Costa-Neto, E. M. 2000. Sustainable Development and Traditional Knowledge. Sustainable Development 8:89–95. Google Scholar

23.

Costa-Neto, E. M., and J. G. W. Marques. 2000. Faunistic Resources Used as Medicines by Artisanal Fishermen from Siribinha Beach, State of Bahia, Brazil. Journal of Ethnobiology 20:93–109. Google Scholar

24.

Cuerrier, A., N. J. Turner, T. C. Gomes, A. Garibaldi, and A. Downing. 2015. Cultural Keystone Places: Conservation and Restoration in Cultural Landscapes. Journal of Ethnobiology 35:427–449. Google Scholar

25.

Daly, L., K. French, T. L. Miller, and L. N. Eoin. 2016. Integrating Ontology into Ethnobotanical Research. Journal of Ethnobiology 36:1–9. Google Scholar

26.

Davidson, D. 1984. Inquiries into Truth & Interpretation. Clarendon Press, Oxford. Google Scholar

27.

Davidson-Hunt, I. J., K. L. Turner, A. T. P. Mead, J. Cabrera-Lopez, R. Bolton, C. J. Idrobo, I. Miretski, A. Morrison, and J. P. Robson. 2012. Biocultural Design: A New Conceptual Framework for Sustainable Development in Rural Indigenous and Local Communities. SAPIENS. Surveys and Perspectives Integrating Environment and Society 5.2. Google Scholar

28.

Dijksterhuis, E. J. 1961. The Mechanization of the World Picture. Calderon Press, Oxford. Google Scholar

29.

Douglas, H. 2009. Science, Policy, and the Value-Free Ideal. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh. Google Scholar

30.

El-Hani, C. N., and R. O. Almeida. In press. Spaces of Encounter and Misencounter between Researchers and Local People in Interdisciplinary and Transdisciplinary Studies in Fishing Villages. In GLOCADEMICS: A Plurilingual, Intercultural and Interdisciplinary Perspective on Transnational Research , edited by M. Guilherme. Multilingual Matters, Bristol. Google Scholar

31.

El-Hani, C. N., and F. P. S. de Ferreira Bandeira. 2008. Valuing Indigenous Knowledge: To Call It ‘Science’ Will Not Help. Cultural Studies of Science Education 3:751–779. Google Scholar

32.

Elkington, J. 2013. Enter the Triple Bottom Line. In The Triple Bottom Line , edited by J. Elkington, pp. 23–38. Routledge, New York. Google Scholar

33.

Ellen, R. 2006. The Categorical Impulse: Essays in the Anthropology of Classifying Behaviour . Berghahn Books, New York-Oxford. Google Scholar

34.

Ellen. R. 2016. Is There a Role for Ontologies in Understanding Plant Knowledge Systems? Journal of Ethnobiology 36:10–28. Google Scholar

35.

Fernández-Llamazares, Á., and V. Reyes-García. 2016. An Ethnobiology of Change. In Introduction to Ethnobiology , edited by U. P. Albuquerque and R. R. N. Alves. pp. 69–74. Springer, Dordrecht. Google Scholar

36.

Fraser, N. 2007. Re-Framing Justice in a Globalizing World. In (Mis)Recognition, Social Inequality and Social Justice , edited by T. Lovell. pp. 29–47. Routledge, New York. Google Scholar

37.

Fraser, N. 2009. Scales of Justice: Reimagining Political Space in a Globalizing World , vol. 31. Columbia University Press, New York. Google Scholar

38.

Fricker, M. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Google Scholar

39.

Gavin, M. C., J. McCarter, A. Mead, F. Berkes, J. R. Stepp, D. Peterson, and R. Tang. 2015. Defining Biocultural Approaches to Conservation. Trends in Ecology & Evolution 30:140–145. Google Scholar

40.

Gomis, A. J. B., M. G. Parra, W. M. Hoffman, and R. E. McNulty. 2011. Rethinking the Concept of Sustainability. Business and Society Review 116:171–191. Google Scholar

41.

Gordon, P. 2004. Numerical Cognition without Words: Evidence from Amazonia. Science 306:496–499. Google Scholar

42.

Graeber, D. 2015. Radical Alterity is Just Another Way of Saying ‘Reality': A Reply to Eduardo Viveiros de Castro. HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5:1–41. Google Scholar

43.

Hansson, S. 2010. Technology and the Notion of Sustainability. Technology in Society 32:274–279. Google Scholar

44.

Henare, A., M. Holbraad, and S. Wastell. 2007. Thinking through Things. Routledge, New York. Google Scholar

45.

Holbraad, M., and M. A. Pedersen. 2017. The Ontological Turn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Google Scholar

46.

Holden, E., K. Linnerud, and D. Banister. 2014. Sustainable Development: Our Common Future Revisited. Global Environmental Change 26:130–139. Google Scholar

47.

Hunn, E. 2014. To Know Them is to Love Them. Ethnobiology Letters 5:46–150. Google Scholar

48.

Hutchison, A. 2014. The Whanganui River as a Legal Person. Alternative Law Journal 39:179–182. Google Scholar

49.

Johannes, R. E. 1989. Traditional Ecological Knowledge. IUCN, Gland. Google Scholar

50.

Johnson, J. T., R. Howitt, G. Cajete, F. Berkes, R. P. Louis, and A. Kliskey. 2016. Weaving Indigenous and Sustainability Sciences to Diversify Our Methods. Sustainability Science 11:1–11. Google Scholar

51.

Kealiikanakaoleohaililani, K., and C. P. Giardina. 2016. Embracing the Sacred: An Indigenous Framework for Tomorrow's Sustainability Science. Sustainability Science 11:57–67. Google Scholar

52.

Khalidi, M. A. 2013. Natural Categories and Human Kinds. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Google Scholar

53.

Kimmerer, R. W. 2012. Searching for Synergy: Integrating Traditional and Scientific Ecological Knowledge in Environmental Science Education. Journal of Environmental Studies and Sciences 2:317–323. Google Scholar

54.

Kincaid, H., J. Dupré, and A. Wylie. 2007. Value-Free Science: Ideals and Illusions? Oxford University Press, Oxford. Google Scholar

55.

Kohn, E. 2013. How Forests Think. University of California Press, Berkeley. Google Scholar

56.

Lansing, J. S. 1991. Priests and Programmers. Princeton University Press, Princeton. Google Scholar

57.

Latulippe, N. 2015. Situating the Work: A Typology of Traditional Knowledge Literature. AlterNative: An International Journal of Indigenous Peoples 11:118–131. Google Scholar

58.

Laudan, L. 1983. The Demise of the Demarcation Problem. In Physics, Philosophy and Psychoanalysis , edited by R. S. Cohen and L. Laudan, pp. 111–127. Springer, Dordrecht. Google Scholar

59.

Lepofsky, D., and S. Wolverton. 2018. Reflecting on Ethnobiology from 1978 to 2018: A Dedication to Steve Weber. Journal of Ethnobiology 38:449–455. Google Scholar

60.

Lertzman, K. 2009. The Paradigm of Management, Management Systems, and Resource Stewardship. Journal of Ethnobiology 29: 339–359. Google Scholar

61.

Lewis-Jones, K. E. 2016. “Useful to Us in Unknown Ways”: Seed Conservation and the Quest for Novel Human-Plant Relationships for the 21st Century. Journal of Ethnobiology 36:66–85. Google Scholar

62.

Ludwig, D. 2016a. Ontological Choices and the Value-Free Ideal. Erkenntnis 81:1253–1272. Google Scholar

63.

Ludwig, D. 2016b. Overlapping Ontologies and Indigenous Knowledge. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 59:36–45. Google Scholar

64.

Ludwig, D. 2017. The Objectivity of Local Knowledge: Lessons from Ethnobiology. Synthese 194:4705–4720. Google Scholar

65.

Ludwig, D. 2018a. Letting Go of ‘Natural Kind'. Towards a Multidimensional Framework of Non-Arbitrary Classification. Philosophy of Science 85:31–52. Google Scholar

66.

Ludwig, D. 2018b. Revamping the Metaphysics of Ethnobiological Classification. Current Anthropology 59:415–438. Google Scholar

67.

Ludwig, D. 2018c. Does Cognition Still Matter in Ethnobiology? Ethnobiology Letters 9:269–275. Google Scholar

68.

Ludwig, D., and L. Poliseli. 2018. Relating Traditional and Academic Ecological Knowledge: Mechanistic and Holistic Epistemologies across Cultures. Biology & Philosophy 33:43. Google Scholar

69.

Marlor, C. 2010. Bureaucracy, Democracy and Exclusion. Qualitative Sociology 33:513–531. Google Scholar

70.

Nabhan, G. P. 2009. Ethnoecology: Bridging Disciplines, Cultures and Species. Journal of Ethnobiology 29:3–8. Google Scholar

71.

Nabhan, G. P., ed. 2016. Ethnobiology for the Future: Linking Cultural and Ecological Diversity. University of Arizona Press, Tucson. Google Scholar

72.

Nadasdy, P. 2003. Hunters and Bureaucrats. UBC Press, Vancouver. Google Scholar

73.

Nolan, J. M., and A. Pieroni. 2014. Introduction to Special Issue on Food Security in a Changing World. Journal of Ethnobiology 34:4–7. Google Scholar

74.

Ott, C. F. 1944. Os elementos culturais da pescaria baiana. Boletim do Museu Nacional 4:1–67. Google Scholar

75.

Poliseli, L. 2018. When Philosophy and Ecology Meet. Unpublished Doctoral Dissertation. Graduate Studies Program in History, Philosophy, and Science Teaching, Federal University of Bahia/State University of Feira de Santana, Brazil. Google Scholar

76.

Putnam, H. 1981. Reason, Truth and History. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Google Scholar

77.

Quine, W. V. 1948. On What There Is. The Review of Metaphysics 2:21–38. Google Scholar

78.

Rose, D. B. 2002. Indigenous Ecologies and an Ethic of Connection. In Global Ethics & Environment , edited by N. Low. pp. 189–201. Routledge, New York. Google Scholar

79.

Saslis-Lagoudakis, C. H., and A. C. Clarke. 2013. Ethnobiology: The Missing Link in Ecology and Evolution. Trends in Ecology & Evolution 28:67–68. Google Scholar

80.

Scott, J. C. 1998. Seeing like a State. Yale University Press, New Haven. Google Scholar

81.

Segundo-Ortin, M., and P. Calvo. 2018. Are Plants Cognitive? A Reply to Adams. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 73:64–71. Google Scholar

82.

Sider, T. 2011. Writing the Book of the World. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Google Scholar

83.

Sillitoe, P. 2006. Ethnobiology and Applied Anthropology: Rapprochement of the Academic with the Practical. Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 12:S119–S142. Google Scholar

84.

Slater, M. H. 2015. Natural Kindness. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66:375–411. Google Scholar

85.

Viveiros de Castro, E. 2014. Cannibal Metaphysics. Univocal Publishing, Minneapolis. Google Scholar

86.

Wanderer, J. 2011. Addressing Testimonial Injustice: Being Ignored and Being Rejected. The Philosophical Quarterly 62:148–169. Google Scholar

87.

WCED (World Commission on Environment and Development). 1987. Our Common Future: Report of the World Commission on Environment and Development. UN Documents Gathering a Body of Global Agreements. Available at:  https://sustainabledevelopment.un.org/content/documents/5987our-common-future.pdfGoogle Scholar

88.

Whyte, K. 2015. How Similar are Indigenous North American and Leopoldian Environmental Ethics? Available at:  http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2022038Google Scholar

89.

Whyte, K. 2018. What Do Indigenous Knowledges Do for Indigenous Peoples? In Traditional Ecological Knowledge: Learning from Indigenous Practices for Environmental Sustainability , edited by M. K. Nelson and D. Shilling, pp. 57–82. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Google Scholar

90.

Whyte, K., and R. Crease. 2010. Trust, Expertise, and the Philosophy of Science. Synthese 177:411–425. Google Scholar

91.

Wilson, S. 2008. Research is Ceremony: Indigenous Research Methods. Fernwood Pub, Halifax. Google Scholar

92.

Wittgenstein, L. 1953. Philosophische Untersuchungen . Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, Frankfurt. Google Scholar

93.

Wolverton, S. 2013. Ethnobiology 5: Interdisciplinarity in an Era of Rapid Environmental Change. Ethnobiology Letters 4:21–25. Google Scholar

94.

Wolverton, S., J. M. Nolan, and W. Ahmed. 2014a. Ethnobiology, Political Ecology, and Conservation. Journal of Ethnobiology 34:125–153. Google Scholar

95.

Wolverton, S., K. J. Chambers, and J. R. Veteto. 2014b. Climate Change and Ethnobiology. Journal of Ethnobiology 34:273–276. Google Scholar

96.

Wolverton, S., R. M. Figueroa, and P. Swentzell. 2016. Archaeology, Heritage, and Moral Terrains: Two Cases from the Mesa Verde Region. Ethnobiology Letters 7:23–31. Google Scholar

97.

Wyndham, F., D. Lepofsky, and S. Tiffany. 2011. Taking Stock in Ethnobiology: Where Do We Come from? What Are We? Where Are We Going? Journal of Ethnobiology 31:110–127. Google Scholar
David Ludwig and Charbel N. El-Hani "Philosophy of Ethnobiology: Understanding Knowledge Integration and Its Limitations," Journal of Ethnobiology 40(1), 3-20, (24 April 2020). https://doi.org/10.2993/0278-0771-40.1.3
Published: 24 April 2020
KEYWORDS
ethnobiological theory
interdisciplinarity
knowledge integration
normativity
philosophy of ethnobiology
Back to Top